About Me

My photo
I have a burning need to know stuff and I love asking awkward questions.

Monday, October 15, 2007

Atheist Ethics (Part 8)

By Julian Baggini

Universalizability

There is something else we could say about why it is bad to cause unnecessary pain which opens the door to another powerful way of thinking about ethics. In each of our own cases we would have no problem in seeing that it is bad for us to suffer unnecessary pain. But if it is bad for us, surely it is also bad for any other creature that could suffer pain in a similar way? If that is true, we have another reason not to cause suffering to others.

This is a very natural line of thought, and versions of the principle that stands behind it have been formulated in various different ways throughout history, from Confucius's golden rule 'Do not do to others what you would not want done to yourself, through Kant's categorical imperative, to the parent who asks their child to consider what would happen if everyone behaved like that. What reasons do we have to accept something like the golden rule? One reason is that we are in danger of acting inconsistently - or to put it more crudely, hypocritically - if we don't. We can see why by thinking about Kant's distinction between what he called hypothetical and categorical imperatives. An imperative is any kind of command such as `you must do X' or `you ought to do X'. Some imperatives hold only with regard to some desired outcome or purpose. For example, if I'm trying to gain weight, then it might be said that I ought to have another cream cake. This 'ought' carries some force only because of my desired goal of gaining weight: I ought to eat the cake only if I want to gain weight. Such an imperative is `hypothetical' in Kant's terminology, meaning that we always need to give some goal or aim to explain why we really ought to do what the imperative commands.

In contrast to these, Kant argued that moral 'oughts' are categorical. I ought not to murder regardless of my aims or objectives. The prohibition is categorical, meaning that we do not need to give some goal or aim to explain why we really ought to follow it. One of the points Kant is making is that this just is the structure of a moral rule. It is the nature of moral rules that they have the form of categorical imperatives. If this is true, then whenever we recognize that we ought to do something or ought not to do something else, we are endorsing a principle that is not relative to the particular interests, desires, or objectives of specific individuals, but universal and applicable to all. So, for example, to recognize that I ought not to be cheated is to recognize that no one ought to be cheated. To be indignant about being cheated while not worrying about cheating others is thus an example of hypocrisy: the arbitrary changing of rules to suit oneself. We need not go as far with Kant to embrace the idea of the categorical imperative to see that some form of universalizability is both an essential feature of moral rules and a natural part of moral reasoning. All we need to get the general principle of universalizability is first to accept that certain things are good or bad if they happen to us, and second to accept that there is no rational reason why, if they are good or bad for us, then they are not also good or bad for other people in similar circumstances. If we accept these two propositions then we have some kind of rational grounding for the principle that we ought not to do unto others what we would object to them doing unto us.

As with all the moral principles I have sketched, we do not have to go too far into the details for things to get difficult and controversial. In this instance, one of the major debates is whether or not universal, categorical imperatives are somehow demanded by reason, as Kant thought, or whether or not the sense in which universalizing moral rules is rational is much weaker. For what it's worth, I think the second response is correct. But as with so many details of moral philosophy, for practical purposes these debates may not matter very much. The very basic principle of universalizability, that if we think something ought to be done in one instance then it ought to be done in other relevantly similar circumstances, commands sufficient agreement and can be used in such a wide range of moral arguments, that technical problems with its formulation and justification are no obstacle to its employment in everyday moral reasoning.

[Universalising morality is another good strand in moral thinking – but yet again not enough in itself to stand as the moral principle. This is actually a good point to make, that no single moral guide is sufficient to answer all of our ethical questions, that guidance should be and needs to be sought from various and diverse sources. Only in this way can we have a truly rounded morality. Kant and other moral philosophers can provide hints, tips and sign posts to help us all think about morality in ways that may be unfamiliar to us. Such unfamiliarity can only prompt us to reconsider the foundations of our own moral thinking and with some effort provide us with a more rational response to the moral questions that arise on a regular basis in everyone’s life.]

4 comments:

Shawn said...

I have to admit that caused a bit of spinning mind syndrome for me...but it was worth it.

I wish more people took the time to look at philosophy and philosophical arguments before jumping into discussions. There's nothing worse than trying to have a logical argument with people who refuse to work within a logical framework.

Thanks for the think.

sirkolgate said...

CK did an eloquent job of summing the ‘moral road’ up.

We do have to ‘think’ about morality and we have to be considerate to other schools of thought. We have to accept that our own ‘moral’ judgment may not be sufficient for every case. We are never done growing morally and throughout life we will look back to things we’ve done and see the ‘error of our ways’.

However, CK I’d argue that you don’t need ‘moral philosophers’ to find yourself morals. I think that anyone who can be patient, kind, sympathetic, and gentle while holding their life to any ‘golden rule’ (Confucius’ or Jesus’) will outstrip most of us.

For all that philosophy and science can do for us there is a hefty load which we bear on our own with what knowledge we’ve always had at hand. The warm embrace of a lover, the gentle soothing of a child, the protection of a comrade, or the peace we give to someone dying. We do not ‘study’ to do these things.

I’d only hazard that we always remember, Atheist, Theist, Communist, Capitalist, Jew, Muslim, Quaker, Eastern Pseudo, or Western Science, is that when it comes to any decision you make regarding the well being of another it is much more simple than all this.

Do not be selfish, conceited, arrogant, angry, rash or distraught in your decisions, but rather take the time to make a calm, collected, justified and thought out decision (if you cannot be this way then make no decision till you are) and that alone will absolve you of about 99% of what makes people do ‘wrong’.

This is just my opinion on the matter, but it is no less correct than the 8 part essay I just read… but no more so either. Just less involved.

CyberKitten said...

sirkolgate said: CK did an eloquent job of summing the ‘moral road’ up.

Thank you.

sirkolgate said: We do have to ‘think’ about morality and we have to be considerate to other schools of thought. We have to accept that our own ‘moral’ judgment may not be sufficient for every case. We are never done growing morally and throughout life we will look back to things we’ve done and see the ‘error of our ways’.

True.

sirkolgate said: However, CK I’d argue that you don’t need ‘moral philosophers’ to find yourself morals.

Also true. It is interesting however to see how they have argued for various moral standpoints over time. It also helps me (at least) to compare their justification for morality and my own personal justifications. I think that if we cannot rational do this then we really don't understand *why* we are behaving in a moral fashion - or even *if* we are.

sirkolgate said: Do not be selfish, conceited, arrogant, angry, rash or distraught in your decisions, but rather take the time to make a calm, collected, justified and thought out decision.

Very laudable aims.... I'm coming to the conclusion that I'm a natural Stoic (of which more later). I do wish that I had access to this philosophical viewpoint in my youth though. It would've saved me a LOT of pain!

sirkolgate said...

CK, I agree that there is a time for deep thinking and conversation, but I'd also suggest that some times there is a danger of 'losing sight of the forest for focusing on the trees'.

That's all...

I'd also hazard to say that most people would say that if you've got to question your morality so thoroughly, then you probably need to.

Have you ever noticed that the greatest minds were often very short and sweet in their most profound statements?

Albert Einstein for example:

"Reality is merely an illusion, albeit a very persistent one."

"Education is what remains after one has forgotten everything he learned in school."

"Whoever undertakes to set himself up as a judge of Truth and Knowledge is shipwrecked by the laughter of the gods."

I especially like that last one, because so many people who make the mistake of thinking that they have cornered the 'market' on cleverness are often quickly overturned, and often by not what they were guarding against.

Anyways, I'm sure some of Al's research papers have a great blast of wordiness, but I think this type of 'wisdom', the type that just makes 'sense' without requiring some vast deliberation is more astute.

In summary... I think simple is best. We live in a world of complexity, but the complexity is of our own creation.

Now I'm not saying, give your money to the church, get a bible, join a convent/monastary, and be 'simple' in these regards.

I just think people would be much happier if they didn't try to 'over' analyze things. There IS such a thing, and by delving into works such as Julian's I believe that's just what we're doing.